Thursday 24 November 2011

Jean Paul Sartre


Não é justo querer lidar com o sofrimento humano sem se engajar na luta contra as causas desses mesmos sofrimentos

~ Jean Paul Sartre

Sartre: karikatur










Saturday 19 November 2011

RENÉ MAGRITTE - sites and life

René François Ghislain Magritte 

* 21 November 1898 – Lessines, BELGIUM
+ 15 August 1967 – Paris

There is so much to talk about Magritte... so many sites, blogs, museum, centres, books, stamps, photographies! By his birthday, just a simple tribute to the greatest master of surrealism.

~ Magritte: anniversaire (1959)


ADAGP - http://bi.adagp.fr/IB_EN/index.php
in PDF - http://issuu.com/michelesato/docs/magritte_adagp

......................

Foundation Magritte
http://www.magritte.be/

René Magritte Museum
http://www.magrittemuseum.be/

Museum Magritte
http://www.fine-arts-museum.be/site/EN/default.asp

Artcyclopedia
http://www.artcyclopedia.com/artists/magritte_rene.html

Wikipedia (En)
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ren%C3%A9_Magritte

Olga’s gallery
http://www.abcgallery.com/M/magritte/magritte.html

Bert Christensen's Cyberspace Gallery
http://bertc.com/g9/index.htm

René Magritte: painting, quote, biography (and video)
http://www.rene-magritte.org/index.jsp

MIMI’s Picasa – n.1
https://picasaweb.google.com/116550716501288513582/ArtMagritteRene1

MIMI’s Picasa – n.2 https://picasaweb.google.com/116550716501288513582/Art_reneMagritte_02?authkey=Gv1sRgCMPA3JGnu_X_uAE

MIMI’s Picasa – photography and draw
https://picasaweb.google.com/116550716501288513582/ArtMagritteRene3Picdraw

MIMI’s Picasa – tributes
https://picasaweb.google.com/116550716501288513582/Art_reneMagritte5_homage

MIMI’s Picasa – ADAGP
https://picasaweb.google.com/116550716501288513582/Art_reneMagritte3Adagp





























ADAGP and archive poster

the archive poster
http://www.artchive.com/artchive/M/magritte.html


Rene Magritte
(1898-1967)


"René Magritte was no doubt disappointed that, aside from the small circle of his kindred spirits among theSurrealists, the world needed over a quarter of a century to discover that his work has both philosophical and poetic content which corresponds to certain social and intellectual trends, particularly of the second half of the twentieth century. Magritte's work was not easy to approach at the outset, however. He is a difficult painter, and his simplicity is misleading. A world ever more disturbed and unstable - in labor, trade, and industry, as well as in intellectual and university circles - is a world in which reason remains indispensable. Yet the irrational no longer allows itself to be thrust aside, and today it is struggling to win recognition. As a result, there is now a greater possibility, especially among the younger generation, to arrive at a better and deeper understanding of Magritte's art.


"His work makes a constant call on us to relinquish, at least temporarily, our usual expectations of art. Magritte never responds to our demands and expectations. He offers us something else instead. His friend Paul Nougé has expressed the problem better than anyone else; what he said in 1944 still holds good: "We question pictures," he said, "before listening to them, we question them at random. And we are astonished when the reply we had expected is not forthcoming."

"Magritte's work allows one to conjure up a state of being which has become rare and precious - which makes it possible to observe in silence. Reading and reflection call for silence, listening no less. Silence can be used for waiting for an illumined vision of things, and it is to this vision that Magritte introduces us.
...
"The fascinating and challenging images in Magritte's works stem from revelations of the mystery of the visible world. To him this world was a more than adequate source of lucid revelations, so that he did not need to draw on dreams, hallucinations, occult phenomena, cabalism. 

Nonetheless, preconsciousness - that is, the state before and during waking up - always played an important role in his work.

"In studying Magritte one begins to understand that attempting to solve puzzles must be avoided but the artist himself provides clues to his manner of painting and the mental process on which it is founded. Some are inclined to call this process "visual thinking. I prefer to give it no name. The term "visual thinking" is not subtle enough and involves too many misunderstandings regarding the possible subordination of the visual to thought, or vice versa. The misunderstanding caused by calling Magritte "cerebral" has also been demonstrated all too often, despite the unusually large quantity of literary, philosophical, and linguistic affinities Magritte's work suggests, and which bring us closer to their meaning. Also the term "literary" is a misconception in his case, although it is understandable because of the literary origins of the leading figures in Surrealism. Let us refrain, then, from favoring one formula or the other and instead take a frank look to see with whom, and with what, Magritte and his marvelous cabinet of instruments can be compared.

"The author who wishes to show complete respect for the struggle Magritte waged against faulty interpretations and explanations - and it was indeed a struggle - nevertheless finds he has to ignore Magritte's own personal ban. Even Magritte himself attempted to explain why he wanted no explanations.

"His pronounced hostility to the idea of the symbol in relation to his work, his undisguised dislike of psychoanalysis in particular, and his distrust of any and every interpretation naturally had reasons. He was defending the very essence of his work by adopting this attitude. If, therefore, we try to understand something of the meaning of his resistance - and Magritte never forbade us to attempt that - we shall come closer to his work by this roundabout way.

"Seeing, says Magritte, is what matters. Seeing must suffice. But what kind of seeing must it be? Of what quality? A form of understanding is possible beyond the confines of any verbal explanation, which, if it is of any use at all, must be authenticated by a way of seeing. Unfortunately, for a large proportion of the public, seeing is not sufficient. People often see things hastily and think about them carelessly; they have been educated in disciplines and traditions in which words represent ideas and have a dominant function. This function has left the realm of revelation beyond words neglected and unexplored.

"Magritte, who was a painter and a painter tout court, albeit an unusual one, was nevertheless more aware than any of his contemporaries of words and of the dubious status they had acquired. His consciousness of words is evident in both his writings and paintings. Dealing with words was a dangerous game to play, though, for by playing it he introduced the element "Word" into his painted "images." Thus, anyone seriously concerned with Magritte's work cannot avoid taking a thorough account of what Magritte sought of words in his work and of the value he attached to them.

"The simplicity in his work is a suspect simplicity. In his writings - which include general articles, a few literary pieces, and special articles on specific themes - and in the titles he gave to his works, Magritte was methodical, as he was in his painting. The unexpected is never mere caprice. Moreover, it resides not so much in Magritte as in ourselves. We are not prepared for, and we do not instantly grasp, his technique of thinking and painting. It is not recalcitrance on his part but a natural need to react to the stereotype phenomena of everyday life in a way contrary to expectation; it is a need to correct. What is more, in Magritte's work this became a discipline of feeling, thinking, and behaving which he discovered and evolved for himself. Accordingly, his method - others feel it was a discipline - is as valid a subject for our inquiry as the works themselves.
"Magritte attempted, as it were, to achieve a controlled resonance in his work. After he had finished a painting, it set up a resonance within him, in which he involved his closest friends. This resonance in the artist himself was necessarily different from that in us, who are the uninitiated in regard to his pictorial and verbal imagery. Yet, despite everything, Magritte probably attached more than usual importance to having people feel the right kind of resonance. That he could do anything about this himself was an illusion; the others were the critics, the art historians, the museums, the art dealers, the collectors, who play their own game with a variety of intentions.

"More often than not, Magritte chose ordinary things from which to construct his works - trees, chairs, tables, doors, windows, shoes, shelves, landscapes, people. He wanted to be understood via these ordinary things. Those who find him obscure should not forget that he had turned his back on the fantastic and on the immediate world of dreams. He did not seek to be obscure. On the contrary, he sought through a therapy of shock and surprise to liberate our conventional vision from its obscurity.

"...[L]et us therefore keep, so far as we can, to Magritte himself, to his own resonance, to his method. Even though his is a complex, sophisticated world in which we often lose sight of simplicity, we are able to find this simplicity again in the works themselves, a fact that can only increase our astonishment."
- Text from "Rene Magritte", by Abraham Marie Hammacher

....................

RENÉ MAGRITTE



réf. : 2T_00295

René MagritteLessines (Belgique) 1898 - Bruxelles (Belgique) 1967
Le libérateur1947
PeintureHuile sur toile100 x 80 cmSigné en bas à gauche "Magritte"Los Angeles, County Museum of Art
SYLVESTER David., "René Magritte, catalogue raisonné", Anvers, Fonds Mercator / Menil Foundation, 1992-1997, vol. 2, n° 630.




réf. : 2T_00303

René MagritteLessines (Belgique) 1898 - Bruxelles (Belgique) 1967
La clef de verre1959
PeintureHuile sur toile130 x 162 cmSigné en bas à gauche "Magritte"Houston, The Menil Collection
SYLVESTER David, "René Magritte, catalogue raisonné", Anvers, Fonds Mercator / Menil Foundation, 1992-1997, vol. 3, pag. 306, n° 899




réf. : 2T_00307

René MagritteLessines (Belgique) 1898 - Bruxelles (Belgique) 1967
Le tombeau des lutteurs1960
PeintureHuile sur toile89 x 116 cmSigné en bas à droite "Magritte"Collection privée
SYLVESTER David., "René Magritte, catalogue raisonné", Anvers, Fonds Mercator / Menil Foundation, 1992-1997, vol. 3, pag. 326, n° 912







Tuesday 15 November 2011

MIA COUTO - mudar o medo

fonte -
http://ebooksgratis.com.br/


Murar o medo – Mia Couto



miacouto [Papo Cabeça] Murar o medo – Mia Couto
Mia Couto, nascido António Emílio Leite Couto, é um biólogo e escritor moçambicano. Chama-se Mia por causa dos gatos: “Eu era miúdo, tinha dois ou três anos e pensava que era um gato, comia com os gatos. Meus pais tinham que me puxar para o lado e me dizer que eu não era um gato. E isto ficou.”

Em uma conferência sobre segurança, realizada em maio de 2011, o poeta-gato fala – com extrema sensibilidade – sobre o medo que nos aprisiona, silencia, o medo que nos impede de olhar o outro e descobrir as belezas do desconhecido. Escutemos, pois, a maravilhosa fala do escritor:



Murar o medo – Mia Couto


O medo foi um dos meus primeiros mestres. Antes de ganhar confiança em celestiais criaturas, aprendi a temer monstros, fantasmas e demónios. Os anjos, quando chegaram, já era para me guardarem, servindo como agentes da segurança privada das almas. Nem sempre os que me protegiam sabiam da diferença entre sentimento e realidade. Isso acontecia, por exemplo, quando me ensinavam a recear os desconhecidos. Na realidade, a maior parte da violência contra as crianças sempre foi praticada não por estranhos, mas por parentes e conhecidos. Os fantasmas que serviam na minha infância reproduziam esse velho engano de que estamos mais seguros em ambientes que reconhecemos. Os meus anjos da guarda tinham a ingenuidade de acreditar que eu estaria mais protegido apenas por não me aventurar para além da fronteira da minha língua, da minha cultura, do meu território.

O medo foi, afinal, o mestre que mais me fez desaprender. Quando deixei a minha casa natal, uma invisível mão roubava-me a coragem de viver e a audácia de ser eu mesmo. No horizonte vislumbravam-se mais muros do que estradas. Nessa altura, algo me sugeria o seguinte: que há neste mundo mais medo de coisas más do que coisas más propriamente ditas.

No Moçambique colonial em que nasci e cresci, a narrativa do medo tinha um invejável casting internacional: os chineses que comiam crianças, os chamados terroristas que lutavam pela independência do país, e um ateu barbudo com um nome alemão. Esses fantasmas tiveram o fim de todos os fantasmas: morreram quando morreu o medo. Os chineses abriram restaurantes junto à nossa porta, os ditos terroristas são governantes respeitáveis e Karl Marx, o ateu barbudo, é um simpático avô que não deixou descendência.

O preço dessa construção [narrativa] de terror foi, no entanto, trágico para o continente africano. Em nome da luta contra o comunismo cometeram-se as mais indizíveis barbaridades. Em nome da segurança mundial foram colocados e conservados no Poder alguns dos ditadores mais sanguinários de que há memória. A mais grave herança dessa longa intervenção externa é a facilidade com que as elites africanas continuam a culpar os outros pelos seus próprios fracassos.

A Guerra-Fria esfriou mas o maniqueísmo que a sustinha não desarmou, inventando rapidamente outras geografias do medo, a Oriente e a Ocidente. E porque se trata de novas entidades demoníacas não bastam os seculares meios de governação… Precisamos de intervenção com legitimidade divina… O que era ideologia passou a ser crença, o que era política tornou-se religião, o que era religião passou a ser estratégia de poder.

Para fabricar armas é preciso fabricar inimigos. Para produzir inimigos é imperioso sustentar fantasmas. A manutenção desse alvoroço requer um dispendioso aparato e um batalhão de especialistas que, em segredo, tomam decisões em nosso nome. Eis o que nos dizem: para superarmos as ameaças domésticas precisamos de mais polícia, mais prisões, mais segurança privada e menos privacidade. Para enfrentar as ameaças globais precisamos de mais exércitos, mais serviços secretos e a suspensão temporária da nossa cidadania. Todos sabemos que o caminho verdadeiro tem que ser outro. Todos sabemos que esse outro caminho começaria pelo desejo de conhecermos melhor esses que, de um e do outro lado, aprendemos a chamar de “eles”.

Aos adversários políticos e militares, juntam-se agora o clima, a demografia e as epidemias. O sentimento que se criou é o seguinte: a realidade é perigosa, a natureza é traiçoeira e a humanidade é imprevisível. Vivemos – como cidadãos e como espécie – em permanente situação de emergência. Como em qualquer estado de sítio, as liberdades individuais devem ser contidas, a privacidade pode ser invadida e a racionalidade deve ser suspensa.

Todas estas restrições servem para que não sejam feitas perguntas [incomodas] como, por exemplo, estas: porque motivo a crise financeira não atingiu a indústria de armamento? Porque motivo se gastou, apenas o ano passado, um trilião e meio de dólares com armamento militar? Porque razão os que hoje tentam proteger os civis na Líbia são exatamente os que mais armas venderam ao regime do coronel Kadaffi? Porque motivo se realizam mais seminários sobre segurança do que sobre justiça?

Se queremos resolver (e não apenas discutir) a segurança mundial – teremos que enfrentar ameaças bem reais e urgentes. Há uma arma de destruição massiva que está sendo usada todos os dias, em todo o mundo, sem que sejam precisos pretextos de guerra. Essa arma chama-se fome. Em pleno século 21, um em cada seis seres humanos passa fome. O custo para superar a fome mundial seria uma fracção muito pequena do que se gasta em armamento. A fome será, sem dúvida, a maior causa de insegurança do nosso tempo.

Mencionarei ainda outra silenciada violência: em todo o mundo, uma em cada três mulheres foi ou será vítima de violência física ou sexual durante o seu tempo de vida… A verdade é que… pesa uma condenação antecipada pelo simples facto de serem mulheres.

A nossa indignação, porém, é bem menor que o medo. Sem darmos conta, fomos convertidos em soldados de um exército sem nome, e como militares sem farda deixamos de questionar. Deixamos de fazer perguntas e de discutir razões. As questões de ética são esquecidas porque está provada a barbaridade dos outros. E porque estamos em guerra, não temos que fazer prova de coerência nem de ética nem de legalidade.

É sintomático que a única construção humana que pode ser vista do espaço seja uma muralha. A chamada Grande Muralha foi erguida para proteger a China das guerras e das invasões. A Muralha não evitou conflitos nem parou os invasores. Possivelmente, morreram mais chineses construindo a Muralha do que vítimas das invasões do Norte. Diz-se que alguns dos trabalhadores que morreram foram emparedados na sua própria construção. Esses corpos convertidos em muro e pedra são uma metáfora de quanto o medo nos pode aprisionar.

Há muros que separam nações, há muros que dividem pobres e ricos. Mas não há hoje no mundo muro que separe os que têm medo dos que não têm medo. Sob as mesmas nuvens cinzentas vivemos todos nós, do sul e do norte, do ocidente e do oriente… Citarei Eduardo Galeano acerca disso que é o medo global:

“Os que trabalham têm medo de perder o trabalho. Os que não trabalham têm medo de nunca encontrar trabalho. Quem não têm medo da fome, têm medo da comida. Os civis têm medo dos militares, os militares têm medo da falta de armas, as armas têm medo da falta de guerras.”

E, se calhar, acrescento agora eu, há quem tenha medo que o medo acabe.

Mia Couto

Saturday 12 November 2011

pinturas escondidas

fonte: fapesp
http://revistapesquisa.fapesp.br/?art=4539&bd=1&pg=1&lg=


Pinturas escondidas
Diagnóstico por imagem traz à tona detalhes ocultos de quadros e obras de arte
© ELIZABETH KAJIYA-IF/USP
No verso do quadro Marinha (à esq.), de Virgilio Guidi, há um retrato feminino, que por sua vez encobre uma cena de Veneza
Nada substitui o olho de um especialista para avaliar as particularidades de um quadro. Mas o emprego em importantes museus e instituições culturais do país de uma série de análises físicas e químicas tornou-se uma ferramenta adicional para entender o estilo e o processo criativo de certos pintores, dar parâmetros ao trabalho de conservação e restauração e trazer à tona facetas ocultas de algumas pinturas. Nesse sentido, a história do quadro Marinha, um óleo sobre madeira produzido provavelmente no início da década de 1940 pelo italiano Virgilio Guidi (1891-1984), é bastante ilustrativa. No catálogo do Museu de Arte Contemporânea da Universidade de São Paulo (MAC-USP), onde se encontra guardada, essa tela abriga, oficialmente, apenas uma pintura: uma vista do Grande Canal de Veneza, com destaque para a Igreja de San Giorgio Maggiore. No entanto, basta virar o quadro para ver, a olho nu, em seu verso o retrato de uma mulher. Imagens no infravermelho desse lado B da tela revelaram uma terceira pintura escondida sob as tintas que deram forma à figura feminina: outra cena marítima da cidade italiana.

A descoberta do trabalho oculto no verso do quadro Marinha foi obtida com o uso de uma técnica óptica não destrutiva denominada reflectografia de infravermelho, que permite ver através das camadas de tinta e, assim, identificar desenhos ocultos pela pintura mais superficial. “Pensávamos que iríamos estudar duas pinturas de Guidi, a da frente e a de trás, mas acabamos descobrindo uma terceira”, diz Márcia Rizzutto, do Instituto de Física da USP, especialista em arqueometria, disciplina que usa métodos científicos para a análise de obras de arte e objetos arqueológicos. A física teve acesso à pintura italiana por meio de uma colaboração de trabalho com a historiadora da arte Ana Gonçalves Magalhães, do MAC, que, num projeto financiado pela FAPESP, está reavaliando e atualizando o catálogo do museu da universidade. “As informações científicas são hoje indispensáveis para o estudo e a conservação de obras de arte”, afirma Ana.

A reflectografia de infravermelho é uma técnica baseada na capacidade de reflexão e absorção que alguns elementos químicos possuem quando sujeitos a ondas eletromagnéticas. As imagens no infravermelho são captadas por uma câmera digital de alta resolução dotada de uma lente com um filtro de luz para esse comprimento de onda. A radiação eletromagnética incidente passa pelas camadas mais externas de tinta até ser absorvida e refletida de volta para a câmera por algum material. O efeito do método é tornar os pigmentos superficiais, que formam a imagem visível a olho nu, mais transparentes e aumentar o contraste de eventuais desenhos de fundo. Cada composto reflete de forma diferente no infravermelho. Pigmentos à base de carbono, muitas vezes utilizados pelos artistas para fazer versões preliminares ou esboços de quadros que posteriormente são cobertos por outras tintas, refletem bem no infravermelho. De acordo com os comprimentos de onda usados nas análises, a espessura das camadas de tintas superficiais e o tipo de pigmentos presentes numa obra, o resultado da equação transparência e contraste pode ser mais favorável à descoberta de surpresas, como a versão do Grande Canal de Veneza que o italiano Guidi preferiu encobrir com um retrato feminino.

A tela Marinha faz parte da Coleção Francisco Matarazzo Sobrinho, composta por 429 obras de artistas brasileiros e do exterior, que pertenceu ao antigo Museu de Arte Moderna de São Paulo e, desde 1963, foi transferida para o acervo do MAC. Em seu trabalho de catalogação das pinturas do museu paulista, Ana priorizou um lote de 70 telas produzidas por pintores italianos na primeira metade do século passado que foram compradas por Ciccillo Matarazzo, como o rico industrial ítalo-brasileiro era mais conhecido, logo após a Segunda Guerra Mundial. Dentro desse subconjunto de telas, cinco quadros chamaram a atenção da historiadora. Eles exibiam pinturas tanto na parte da frente como também no verso.

As obras que estavam na frente são as que Ciccillo oficialmente comprou. Sobre elas há informações nos registros do museu. As que estão na parte de trás, mesmo quando visíveis a olho nu, não têm documentação ou apresentam registros incompletos. “Nesses casos, Ciccillo comprou uma obra e acabou levando duas, a da frente e a de trás”, afirma Ana. A tela de Guidi é um caso extremo, em que há três pinturas no mesmo suporte, sendo uma invisível a olho nu. Por sinal, graças ao trabalho de catalogação da historiadora se descobriu que a figura feminina retratada no verso era a mulher do artista italiano.
Retoques revelados - Outro caso interessante é o da pintura Nu inacabado, um óleo sobre tela de 1943 de autoria do italiano Felice Casorati (1883-1963), que também compõe a Coleção Francisco Matarazzo Sobrinho. O quadro, devidamente catalogado no MAC, mostra uma mulher despida sentada numa cadeira. No verso da pintura aparece uma segunda obra, também visível a olho nu, sobre a qual não havia nenhuma informação: o retratro de um menino. Márcia Rizzutto fez imagens das duas pinturas usando diferentes métodos, como a reflectografia de infravermelho e também a fluorescência de luz ultravioleta. “Essa segunda técnica permite visualizar informações superficiais da camada pictórica e detectar sujidades, fungos, rasgos, fissuras e áreas retocadas”, explica a física da USP. Quando expostos à radiação ultravioleta, alguns materiais usados nas pinturas, como os diferentes tipos de verniz, tornam-se fluorescentes. Áreas retocadas, em que o verniz original foi removido e recoberto por outro pigmento, aparecem como manchas escuras quando vistas com essa técnica.

As imagens de ambos os lados do quadro obtidas com essas duas técnicas distintas evidenciaram que o estilo das pinturas era diferente. Casorati desenhou a cena do nu, com algum pigmento à base de carbono, antes de adicionar cor a ela. Já o autor do retrato do menino tinha um estilo mais impressionista. Não há desenho a carvão e o artista pintou fazendo pequenos borrões com a tinta. Essas informações, aliadas a uma pesquisa histórica sobre a vida de Casorati, levaram Ana a uma descoberta: a figura do menino foi pintada por Daphne Maugham Casorati (1897-1982), mulher de Casorati e mãe do garoto.

Às vezes, o casamento entre as várias técnicas de arqueometria e a análise artística das pinturas não produz resultados aparentemente tão espetaculares, como nos casos dos estudos das obras de Guidi e Casorati. Ainda assim, traços insuspeitos de uma pintura podem vir à tona quando a ciência joga luz sobre um quadro. Na tela A adivinha, do italiano Achille Funi (1890-1972), outro óleo sobre madeira da coleção de Ciccillo Matarazzo, Márcia e Ana perceberam que parte do cenário de fundo do lado direito da obra, onde havia uma parede e uma porta em arco, foi coberta por uma tinta escura. Por algum motivo, Funi mudou de ideia e ocultou essa parte do background. “Descobrimos alterações que os pintores fazem e não incorporam à obra final por meio da análise dos diversos tipos de imagem que podemos obter de um quadro”, diz Ana. Por sinal, esse quadro, embora não tenha nenhuma pintura oculta ou visível no verso, é inédito para a historiografia internacional e não consta do catálogo geral da obra de Funi na Itália.
Rotina de museu - Em grandes museus da Europa e dos Estados Unidos, como o Louvre em Paris, a National Gallery de Londres e o Metropolitan de Nova York, as análises arqueométricas já se incorporaram à rotina das instituições há décadas. Os próprios estabelecimentos contam com aparelhos e pessoal qualificado para fazer os estudos, não sendo necessário, em alguns casos, nem recorrer a parcerias com os pesquisadores de universidades. Aqui os museus começaram a se abrir para esse tipo de colaboração há poucos anos. Na Pinacoteca do Estado de São Paulo, por exemplo, toda peça que hoje entra no acervo passa obrigatoriamente por cinco exames: uma análise organoléptica (feita por um especialista em arte) e obtenção de imagens no infravermelho, ultravioleta, luz rasante (para detectar desníveis e fraturas na pintura) e luz transversa.
 1  2 Próxima


(Página 2 de 2)
© ELIZABETH KAJIYA-IF/USP
Imagens na luz visível e no infravermelho (embaixo) da tela A adivinha, de Achille Funi: detalhes do fundo do quadro são destacados por técnicas da arqueometria
A maioria dos exames é feita no próprio museu. Em alguns casos, os quadros têm de ser levados até o Institudo de Física da USP, onde são realizados estudos dos pigmentos ou radiografias. “Essas análises foram incorporadas à documentação das obras”, diz Valeria de Mendonça, coordenadora do núcleo de conservação e restauro da Pinacoteca. “Elas serão úteis para eventuais restaurações no futuro e para pesquisas sobre o estilo de artistas.” Valeria calcula que cerca de 100 obras da Pinacoteca já foram alvo de exames arqueométricos pela equipe de Márcia. No momento há um grande estudo em curso, em parceria com a USP, sobre as características estilísticas e os tipos de pigmento usados pelo pintor brasileiro Oscar Pereira da Silva (1867-1939). A Pinacoteca dispõe de uma dezena de pinturas do artista, que são um bom material de análise.

Algumas técnicas arqueométricas permitem discriminar os pigmentos originalmente usados por um artista e diferenciar as tintas que foram posteriormente empregadas em restaurações da obra. A química Cristiane Calza, do Laboratório de Instrumentação Nuclear da Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro (Coppe/UFRJ), conta com um sistema portátil de fluorescência de raios X que tem produzido resultados interessantes quando seu feixe é apontado para telas e esculturas. Recentemente, com a ajuda do aparelho, a pesquisadora identificou 10 diferentes camadas de tinta na antiga estátua de São Sebastião da Igreja dos Capuchinhos, no Rio de Janeiro.

A camada original, que remete ao século XVI, quando a obra foi trazida de Portugal por Estácio de Sá, era composta pelo branco de chumbo misturado com um pouco devermilion (à base de sulfeto de mercúrio). “Esse pigmento tinha o intuito de conferir um tom rosado à pele”, diz Cristiane. A composição da segunda à quinta camadas era a mesma da primeira, com maior ou menor adição de vermilion ao branco de chumbo. Na sexta e sétima camadas aparecem pigmentos que começaram a ser utilizados no século XIX: litopônio (um branco obtido com a mistura de sulfato de bário e sulfeto de zinco) e o vermelho ocre. Na oitava ressurge o branco de chumbo, agora misturado ao ocre evermilion. Na nona há branco de zinco e ocre. Na última e atual camada, legado de um restauro realizado no século XX, foi caracterizado o emprego de branco de zinco, branco de titânio e ocre. “Com essas informações é possível pensar numa restauração da estátua que tente preservar as características originais da obra”, afirma Cristiane.
Os projetos
1. Reavaliação crítica e atualização da catalogação do acervo do MAC-USP - nº 2009/01041-7
2. Feixe externo de íons para caracterização não destrutiva de objetos arqueológicos e obras de arte do patrimônio cultural - nº 2007/08721-8
ModalidadeAuxílio Regular a Projeto de Pesquisa
Co­or­de­na­doras
1. Ana Gonçalves Magalhães – MAC-USP
2. Márcia Rizzutto – IF-USP
Investimento1. R$ 18.400,00 (FAPESP)
2. US$ 38.000,00 e R$ 34.500,00 (FAPESP)

Thursday 10 November 2011

O Facebook é antidemocrático?


fonte - observatório da imprensa

REDES SOCIAIS
O Facebook é antidemocrático?
Por Renato Essenfelder em 08/11/2011 na edição 667

O domínio das chamadas redes sociais avança na internet – e fora dela. Pesquisa do Forrester Research divulgada no último dia 3 de novembro aponta que nada menos do que 96% de todos os internautas adultos dos Estados Unidos têm um perfil no Facebook. Na sequência vem a rede profissional LinkedIn, com 28% de adesão, e o Twitter (24%) – este, mais popular entre os mais jovens. Considerando sobreposições, é possível afirmar que simplesmente todos os cidadãos americanos com mais de 18 anos de idade estão representados por um ou mais perfis virtuais atualmente.

No Brasil não é diferente. A tendência, a despeito da desigualdade social e da ainda claudicante democratização dos meios de acesso à rede, é de representação total. Conforme escreveu nesteObservatório Marília Massochin, as crianças brasileiras “saem na frente dos outros países em relação à utilização das redes sociais. Mais de 11% do total de meninas e meninos de dois a 11 anos usam as mídias sociais no território nacional, enquanto a média global não passa de 7%”. Segundo dados do Ibope Nielsen Online citados pela autora, já se contabiliza 5,2 milhões de crianças brasileiras entre dois e11 anos navegando na internet.


“A democracia de todos é mentira”

Caminhamos para a representação total. Além disso, lembrando artigo do professor da ECA-USP e colega de ESPM Eugenio Bucci publicado no Estado de S.Paulo e reproduzido neste Observatório, a internet não deve ser tratada como mero meio de comunicação – e ainda menos como um meio de comunicação de massa. Isso, argumenta o pesquisador, é reduzi-la excessivamente. Escreve Bucci:

“Ela [a internet] é tão ampla como são amplas as atividades humanas: aceita declarações de amor, assim como aceita lances ousados da especulação imobiliária. Nela, a vida social alcança plenamente outro nível, que não é físico, mas é real, tão real que afeta diretamente o mundo físico, sendo capaz de transformá-lo. Mais que meio de comunicação, a internet é, antes, a sociedade num segundo grau de abstração. Se quiserem comparações, ela tem mais semelhança com a rede de energia elétrica do que com um aparelho de TV ou com o alto-falante na praça do coreto.”

Não se pode negar a sabedoria dessa constatação, mas, ao mesmo tempo, parece igualmente perigoso estendê-la à utopia da internet como substituto de instituições de representação democrática, como alertou o espanhol Jesús Martín-Barbero em entrevista a este autor publicada na Folha de S. Paulo em 2009 (leia a íntegra aqui). Barbero repudia o uso do termo “comunidade” para caracterizar o que acontece nas redes sociais hoje, e avança:

“No conceito de comunidade há sempre a tentação de devolver-nos a uma certa relação não mediada, presencial. Essa é um pouco a utopia da internet: que já não necessitamos ser representados. A democracia é de todos, somos todos iguais. Mentira. Nunca fomos, nem somos, nem seremos iguais. E, portanto, a democracia de todos é mentira. Seguimos necessitando de mediações de representação das diferentes dimensões da vida. Precisamos de partidos políticos ou de uma associação de pais em um colégio, por exemplo.”


“Uma nova forma de fazer sociedade”

Seguindo o raciocínio de Barbero, é possível dizer que as comunidades virtuais que unem telespectadores da novela das 21h ou fãs de Justin Bieber são um arranjo social (para o qual ainda não há, diz, uma nomenclatura ou reflexão solidamente formulados), mas ao mesmo tempo têm pouco de comunidade – no sentido pré-moderno. Encontramos raciocínio análogo no polonês Zygmunt Bauman, que em 2003 lançouComunidade: a Busca por Segurança no Mundo Atual. Segundo o sociólogo, comunidade é um arranjo com “compartilhamento fraterno”, em que a liberdade individual é parcialmente posta de lado em nome de um sentimento de segurança de grupo. E, na contemporaneidade “líquida” e individualista, isso não ocorre.

Vale lembrar que o professor da PUC-SP Rogério da Costa, em ótimo artigo sobre a questão, detecta um certo ar nostálgico em Bauman, um querer aplicar ideias antigas a um fenômeno novo, o que “seria simplesmente se impedir de ver o que vem acontecendo nos movimentos coletivos de nossa época”. Barbero não é tão nostálgico quanto Bauman, pois admite que “há muitas coisas a repensar radicalmente” hoje, inclusive o conceito de comunidade e sua aplicabilidade às redes sociais.

Pierre Levy, em “Cyberdemocracia”, radicalmente oposto aos “nostálgicos”, diz que as comunidades virtuais são “uma nova forma de fazer sociedade”. “Essa nova forma é rizomática, transitória, desprendida de tempo e espaço, baseada muito mais na cooperação e trocas objetivas do que na permanência de laços. E isso tudo só foi possível com o apoio das novas tecnologias de comunicação”, escreve.


Não somos iguais, nem na rede nem na vida

O problema, reitera Barbero, é quando, imbuídos do pior espírito de panaceia, cremos que redes como o Facebook, que criam laços reais entre as pessoas, possam substituir mecanismos historicamente testados de representação, como os partidos políticos. É a utopia da democracia direta, sem mediação: para que votar em um candidato do partido X ou Y se posso eleger diretamente o perfil da pessoa com que mais me identifico? E o mesmo raciocínio falacioso se estende ao jornalismo: para que jornalistas se posso me informar sobre o que me importa diretamente através do Twitter e congêneres? A realidade, no entanto, não condiz com a euforia exagerada dos que creem na internet como início e fim de tudo.

E Barbero ainda provoca: “O site é real, mas a maneira como nos relacionamos, como o usamos, é muito distinta. O Facebook não nos iguala. Nos põe em contato, mas nada mais”.Nesse sentido, retomamos a ideia de Bucci: a internet está mais para uma “segunda realidade” do que para um meio de comunicação. Paradoxalmente, o ambiente “ultrademocrático” de um Facebook pode se mostrar nocivo à democracia, à medida que estimula um esvaziamento da participação na cena política da “primeira realidade” em que nos inserimos.

Nessa segunda realidade, ressalte-se, seguimos necessitando de mecanismos de representação – ela não os substitui, mas, pelo contrário, sofistica a demanda por sistemas de curadoria, reputação e representação social, ao mesmo tempo em que pode nos ajudar a oxigenar e aperfeiçoar as instituições que historicamente têm prestado serviços à democracia, como partidos políticos, sindicatos, associações e agremiações diversas.

Não somos todos iguais, nem na rede nem na vida. Por isso o edifício democrático não se encerra no clicar de botões ou na constatação de que temos tantos seguidores virtuais. O esforço de sua construção permeia todas as realidades, permanentemente.

***

[Renato Essenfelder é editor e professor de Jornalismo das universidades Mackenzie e ESPM, em São Paulo, doutorando em Ciências da Comunicação pela ECA-USP e membro da Joseph Campbell Foundation]

Tuesday 8 November 2011

surrealism, dada and the refusal work

oxford art journal
http://oaj.oxfordjournals.org/content/34/1/79.full





Surrealism, Dada, and the Refusal of Work: Autonomy, Activism, and Social Participation in the Radical Avant-Garde

Gavin Grindon


Discussions of the relatively recent notion of ‘activist-art’ have two common art-historical frames. The first is formal: the post-modern move towards collective or participatory art practices.1 The second is critical and historical: that of the revolutionary ambitions of the historical avant-garde, and their ‘failure’ or ‘success'. This frame, made central by Peter Bürger in 1974, has produced a wealth of criticism.2 Perhaps due to this weight of criticism, these two frames are often considered in isolation from one another. Meanwhile, the narrative of the failure of the radical avant-garde3 project has become a common one. However, this tragic historical narrative is far less clear cut than it is often presumed to be. Against these melancholy readings of history, it is possible to trace another, joyful, trajectory: a history not of the failure of the radical avant-garde, but of its success. But rather than defending the ‘success’ of later ‘neo-avant-garde’ art, this article will attempt to offer a historical rethinking of the frame of radical avant-gardism in the art and writing of Dada and Surrealism by drawing on the ideas of autonomist Marxist theorists such as Antonio Negri, Mario Tronti, and others.4 This is a tradition that, while still Marxist, is opposed to the philosophical Western Marxist tradition5 to which Bürger belongs in its emphasis on the primacy of revolutionary agency over ideological critique. This reappraisal of the radical avant-garde begins by examining the theme of the refusal of work in Surrealism and Dadaism.6But to do so first necessitates a critical return to accounts of the avant-garde's use or negation of the autonomy of art, alongside an examination of their engagement with cultural practices beyond this autonomy.
Previous SectionNext Section
On Strike against Society: Aesthetic and Political Autonomy

In the bourgeois era, as cultural production was enclosed by the market and art was increasingly separated from the social institutions which had previously supported and conditioned it, a theoretical tendency emerged which conceived of art as self-governing and autonomous from other social institutions: what is usually called ‘the autonomy of art'. The ideological character of this autonomy, which is bound up with bourgeois ideas of a free, independently rational subject, has been accounted for by a number of Marxist critics.7 However, in writing on art and aesthetics from the Romantic period onwards, this idea also began to appear to celebrate a subjective freedom to, as well as a freedom-from, often variously aligned with radical positions opposed to capitalism. One can sense this tension, for example, in Mallarmé’s ambiguous assertion of art's autonomy via a metaphor of social engagement, when he claims that ‘in our time the poet can only go on strike against society'.8 In the early twentieth century, these divergent tendencies reach a point of crisis. The freedom implied by aesthetic autonomy began to be taken to imply a freedom beyond the limits of aesthetic production. This is the historical condition of possibility of the avant-garde which Bürger describes as ‘the systemic self-criticism of art'.9 This situation was a result of historical changes in the composition of the role of ‘artist'. The aesthetic discourses above diagnose the artist as a peculiar figure. As an ideal of genius and creation, the artist is celebrated for a rejection of measure and fixity, and provides a refuge of non-normative behaviour. In others words, the artist was a sovereign figure. But, in Modernity, the class-relations which support this sovereignty altered and threw it into crisis, in the separation which emerges between art's social autonomy (artistic production's functional, institutional separation from its earlier economic basis, in the move from aristocratic patronage to a market system – that is, a move into more openly performing a social role) and the ideological value, or cultural capital, which remained around this work and its products: its autonomy as a value.

Bürger's Theory of the Avant-Garde defines the radical avant-garde as an attempt to bring art into everyday life. However, Bürger argues that this self-critical Icarian vault is doomed by its historical inheritance. He characterises the avant-garde as an attempt to dialectically realise the autonomous value of the bourgeois artwork; an attempt which ended in tragic failure. Its subversive anti-art works, intended as a refusal of art and of the commodity-form, were bought up as artworks and commodities. After this, history repeats itself as farce. The ‘neo-avant-garde’ exemplified by Warhol's pop art produces a neo-Dadaism which repeats the rejection of art as art, in ‘a manifestation that is void of sense'.10 The avant-garde has become impossible. He concludes that the avant-garde's political strategies are dead. But it is possible to locate an open element in this smooth dialectical narrative, a minor thread which breaks with it. Bürger's reading has been powerful and valuable in identifying one set of limits to art that has attempted political critique or counter-representation within the commodity-form, which the avant-garde were first to experience. However, it does so by exclusively emphasising that the autonomy of art is an ideological value which is a function of the commodity-form. But it is possible to make a reading of this autonomy-as-a-value which also emphasises both its positive content despite its basis, and the re-articulation of this content in relation to non-commodity social forms and relations. Such a reading throws positive light on other less tragic strategies of the radical avant-garde.

It is possible to sketch a brief genealogical reading of this autonomy-as-a-value and its positive content. The autonomy of art held a positive sense of embodied autonomous labour-power. This positive sense of art's autonomy was already present in nascent form in earlier articulations of aesthetic autonomy. The establishment of aesthetics as a separate sphere of knowledge, and a conception of artistic production as an activity distinct from all other social production, is articulated through a complex dialectic between notions of work and play, purpose, and disinterest. There is not space to explore this fully here, but it perhaps finds its clearest articulation in Schiller's 1795 Aesthetic Education of Man, in which he argues that artistic production and aesthetic contemplation resolve the rational and sensuous aspects of man in the form of a play drive. This harmonious free play of one's faculties embodies the autonomy of art such that ‘man …is only fully a human being when he plays'.11 This moral function attributed to play owes much to Kant, who makes a distinction between crude ‘mere enjoyment’, excluded from his definition of the aesthetic, and ‘disinterested’ play. Nonetheless, disinterested play serves an edifying moral purpose for him, too. These tensions reflect a historical fact, which Bürger notes, that the formation of a sovereign aesthetic, disinterested and non-instrumental, reflects the development that for classes among whom, ‘at least at times, are free from the pressures of the need of survival, a sensuousness could evolve that was not part of any means-ends relationship'. This ‘moment of truth’12 in theories of art's autonomy can be read as an ambiguous and perverse ideological valorisation of labour-power. Not only was this freedom from labour the reverse of the medal of the mass social creativity enclosed by capital in the rise of these classes, but also the cultural valorisation of freedom, creativity, and individuality in the autonomy of art also enshrined its economic values. Yet, this ambiguous tension between aesthetic play and capitalist work meant that it was possible for the notion of art as play to be reactively articulated against work. The sovereignty of art, expressed in autonomy-as-a-value's ideal of free play, could be imagined as allied with attacks on other forms of sovereignty, such as that of capital or the state.

This imagination is, for Bürger (and many other Western Marxist critics), subject to an ideological critique in which autonomy-as-a-value's embodiment of life's unfulfilled ideals, enclosed in the commodity-form, can only serve to affirm, legitimate, and stabilise a capitalist society. For Bürger, the form of the separation is conditioned by a ‘negative’ reading of autonomy-as-a-value purely as embodied reification, as separation from life, which the avant-garde then attempts to realise.13 In this argument, beginning with the capitalist products of art-work in the alienated commodity-form of art, autonomy-as-a-value is only ever circularly defined within the limits of the commodity-form. In crude terms, art is defined ultimately only a function of exchange value. However, focusing on this positive aspect of autonomy-as-a-value, it is possible to identify it functioning, despite its contradictions, also as a language for, and a means to imagine, other forms of rupture with the institutions of art and the commodity-form which the above accounts’ critical programme is blind to. Radical aspects of Romanticism had already formulated a celebration of creative vitality as an ‘impossible’ return to play, childhood, or nature contra capital, the urban centre and work, yet coupled to a cult of paralysed retreat into isolation, poverty, madness, and death. But this potential counter-valorisation of play was placed in a new context as the relative composition of ‘work’ and ‘free’ time altered in the West from the late nineteenth century onward. These valorisations of play came into coincidence with the increased visibility of play as an other to high culture, both through the colonial project (for example in the work of Herbert Spencer and Karl Groos)14 and through the rise of urban mass culture and leisure. The new spaces, practices, and objects of leisure and non-work time made possible, and were often the site of, the avant-garde's valorisation of play in new terms. The play-ideal embedded in the autonomy of art could be reiterated as a refusal of work. Art's autonomy-as-a-value provided the language for a move from subjection, the negative disciplinary definition of a subject by discourse, to subjectification: the self-creation of a new subject-position through the imagination and performance of other forms of (artistic, social) subjectivity. For many avant-garde groups, the role of ‘artist’ would be appended to other imaginations of labour-identity. Other values were articulated through the language of the autonomy of art, within and against the ideological discourses it was taken from, which forged a new political language of sovereignty. The values of bourgeois art provided a hope that exceeded their basis. Through attention to this positive aspect of autonomy-as-a-value, it is possible to identify less visible forms of artistic-political engagement amongst these groups. Perhaps, not accidentally, the moment of the radical avant-garde's disappearance from art histories is a crucial moment of its success as a radical tendency.
Previous SectionNext Section
Surrealism and the Refusal of Work

For some artists, the systemic self-criticism of art meant autonomy-as-a-value comes to stand for something other than the production of art objects. The working role of the ‘artist’ is thrown into crisis. Avant-gardes often did not conceive of themselves as a vanguard of artists leading the way, but as artists refusing the role of artists. This rupture with the idea of art was bound up with a rupture with the idea of work, which became a common theme among avant-garde groups, for whom dissidence was a matter of disidentity. The abolition of art was first a self-abolition. Proclamations of this suicide of the author arose particularly consistently in Surrealist statements by André Breton, Louis Aragon, and André Thirion, in different contexts between 1920 and 1930. Aragon, performing a manifesto later published in the journal of the group of Parisian Dadaists that would become the Surrealists, announced, ‘No more painters, no more writers, no more musicians, no more sculptors … enough of all these imbecilities, no more, no more, no more, no more, no more'.15 Helena Lewis details how in the initial period of Surrealism, ‘all literary and artistic productions had to be approved by the group before they could be published or exhibited’ and ‘regular work, especially anything that could lead to a successful career, was forbidden'.16 In 1925, issue two of Surrealist Revolution contained an essay by Breton attacking the sacred character of work.17 The ideas’ centrality was reiterated by a collective declaration the same year, ‘We have nothing to do with literature … .We are specialists in Revolt’18 and issue four came unambiguously emblazoned with the slogan ‘And War On Work’ across its cover. By 1929, André Thirion would produce the most developed Surrealist expression of this position in an article, ‘Down With Work',19 whilst the dissident Surrealist Georges Bataille wrote, in his first essay on the political meaning of Surrealism, thatWe must insist from the outset that a still relatively new form of intellectual activity, not yet castrated and domesticated, is linked by the force of things to the uprising of the lower classes against present-day work.20Having earlier written that ‘there is no use being alive if one must work',21 Breton attempted, in the Second Surrealist Manifesto, to reassert the centrality of this refusal even as it slipped from view:There are still today, in the lycées, even in the workshops, in the street, the seminaries and military barracks, pure young people who refuse to knuckle down. It is to them and them alone that I address myself, it is for them alone that I am trying to defend Surrealism against the accusation that it is, after all, no more than an intellectual pastime like any other.22The Surrealists would also codify their refusal of work partly through a dis-identitarian pantheon of those who assert ‘I am an other’, from cultural figures such as Rimbaud and Sade; Chaplin the clown and Fantômas the criminal; to a celebration of contemporary lumpen vagabondage, in their own heroes of the art of living, Arthur Cravan and Jacques Vaché. This tendency persisted elsewhere, too. Aragon later presented hisTreatise on Style not as an aesthetic guide to writing, but an ethical guide to living in which ‘it is necessary to study the episodic forms of rebellion'.23 This Surrealist emphasis on the refusal of work was a product of autonomy-as-a-value's systemic self-criticism of the role of the artist. Neither was this an aristocratic gesture of personal retreat or of pure negation. Instead, as I will argue below, this rhetorical refusal to participate in the production of capitalist values was one side of the avant-garde's positive participation in composing alternatives. Most negative accounts of the bold claims of the avant-garde for art's potential to change society, by focusing on recuperation and commodity-fetishism, overlook the ‘other labour’ which often lay behind the refusal of work.
Previous SectionNext Section
Aesthetic Composition

To examine this other labour, I would like to place the radical avant-garde in the context of the history of labour studies. This might seem an unusual perspective,24 but framing these issues in terms of the changing role of what Marx called labour-power25 rather than the critique of ideology reveals another possible narrative of the avant-garde.26 We can read the radical avant-garde from this perspective by drawing on the notion of ‘class composition’ in autonomist Marxist thought. There is a long, albeit fragmented, critical discourse on work and its composition. Marx uses the term ‘the composition of capital’ to account for capital as, at any one point, made up of a particular organisation of the ratio between living and dead labour. Autonomists have since proposed to view things from the other side, asserting the composition of the working class against capital. Class composition27 rejects the idea of a working-class perspective ‘valid for all human history’28 or that this perspective could be identified with a particular philosophical method. Instead, it attempted to measure the actually existing form of the working class. The term denotes two antagonistic forces. On the one hand, technical composition – the shaping of the working class by the demands of capital, for example, by management discipline and economic restructuring. On the other hand, political composition – the composition from below of the working class as a force against capital, in the everyday emergence of new forms of work-refusal, subversion, and organisation.29 This analyses places in Marxist terms what Foucault termed ‘subjection’ and ‘subjectification’30 – labouring participation in the making of one's identity and social relations.

This attention to labour and identity is intended to address a methodological gap. Though art history is sensitive to subjective aesthetic encounters with objects and performances, its social extension of these has mostly addressed them through ideological critique. Conversely, the potential agency of performances and objects in ordering the social world has been explored by anthropological studies of material culture, but these have tended to be structural and macropolitical. This is even more so the case for Sociology, despite focusing a specific field of studies, for example, on the culture of social movements. Addressing art in terms of labour studies, and class composition specifically, allows us to appreciate the moving aesthetics of such encounters, whilst also exploring the connection between affect and social movement. Class composition has been compared with Foucault's notion of biopower, but, unlike his critique of governmentality and control, focuses on biopower in production.31 Both consider the ‘base’ of social reproduction not only as economic but also as cultural, bodily, and subjective. As such, we can complement the autonomist approach to subjective agency in historical materialism with more recent broadly post-structural accounts of a materialism that is affective and performative.32 The notion of political composition identifies as political moments of otherwise invisible or illegible performative social relation. These are often primarily affective, emotional, sensory and possess a fugitive history in official discourses, even as they compose more visible social struggles.33 In this way affect, central to biopower, has a role in producing and reproducing society. As will hopefully become clear, this perspective is helpful in grasping the particular aesthetic-social condition and role of activist-art forms, in that these forms are irreducible to and cross the critical divisions of ‘art’ and ‘propaganda', or ‘aesthetics’ and ‘ethics'. In the above analysis, aesthetics and affect play a materialist role in the composition of social identities, fostering some relations and not others, and we might speak in terms of aesthetic or affective composition. As a compound noun, affective composition denotes a particular situation or relationship, connected to what is termed at the broadest social level, ‘emotional habitus’ by Gould or ‘structure of feeling’ by Williams.34 It can be addressed as both technical and political.

Political composition offers a means to focus on relations of cultural and social production partly outside or against capitalist relations. This other production has been explored by, for example, Rancière's Nights of Labour: The Workers’ Dream in Nineteenth Century France, but for a collective model of artistic production, we might look to the context of social movements,35 which have their own art taking the form of material culture and performance, which developed not from a tradition of aesthetic autonomy but of social conflict. Accounts of such art have usually been divided amongst several analytical categories of extra-institutional art, as political ‘propaganda’; socially-marginal ‘outsider art’ or treated anthropologically, as ‘folk art'. Instead, we might identify an independent history of unique properties and values in the art of social movements. This art is unabashedly instrumental. E.P. Thompson provides a seminal example in his study of ‘rough music’ in Britain, a very broad set of popular folk-cultural performances which he identified from at least the late seventeenth century, part of a broader European practice of charivari. As a ritual collective performance and an act of social ordering, it could involve a din of various instruments, pots and pans, laughter and obscenity, inverted values (blasphemy, transvestism), humiliation and often mock-funeral processions, concluding in the destruction of an effigy. It was directed against those who broke the order of a community, and became central to the cultural vocabulary of popular dissent and demonstration.36 In the nineteenth century, such forms became increasingly homogenous:Action in the eighteenth-century repertoire differentiated greatly according to the task at hand and the setting; one donkeyed a weaver who worked for less than the locally-agreed rate; gave Rough Music to a wife-beater; wrecked the house of an unscrupulous baker, and the exact routine …varied from region to region. Nineteenth century Britons had far fewer choices, but applied them to a much wider range of problems.37Thereafter, the forms of social movement art become those we are most familiar with, associated with the urban crowd. Like Saint-Simon's notion of an avant-garde, the forms which developed, whether banners and posters; parades and marches; or even barricades, borrowed from the existing religious and military arts of disciplining, ordering, and composing a mass of people as much as from eighteenth-century popular folk culture.

Modernity represented a new high-point of technical composition. The war encouraged the rapid development of a mechanised factory system and a new wave of technological development. In 1911, Frederick Taylor published his Principles of Scientific Management, which extended the logic of Fordist production into the micro-control of working subjects. We can read this text as a capitalist reiteration of governmental discourses of subjection. Taylor's text develops a particular Modernist discourse on performance and identity in the field of business strategy. Taylor understood the identity of worker not as a fixed status but as a role which may be more or less well performed. His ‘process management’38 and its attempt to control workflows tied the gestures and movements that make up the performance of the role of worker to the economicperformance of a company as a whole. In this discourse, performance was a synonym for success or failure: a term of measure of surplus value and exploitation which could be either ‘high’ or ‘low’. The greater the increase in Fordist machine-production and the attunement of its various parts, the smaller the affective play-element of work's performance became. Taylorism's micro-discipline made the subjective refusal of work a primary, if rarely documented, class battleground. The linear ground of performance as a measure was opposed by performing otherwise, refusing the role of worker by developing other techniques producing valorisations other to that of capital. Taylor's work was archetypal of another utopian imagination of the future: an intensified pace of ‘rationalised’ social performance after World War I. This discipline of the identity of worker coincided with a turn to address ‘use’ in culture, as maintaining the effective or efficient performance of social roles. Following Taylor, and in France Henri Foyol, there was an attempt to shape the performance of ‘free’ time outside of work in rational managerial–governmental terms. Society, too, was a factory that required management. Many began to imagine a culture expressing this industrial logic in machine-metaphors, against accounts of culture as without use. Courbusier would famously rethink the architecture of the home as a ‘machine for living'.39 Others would apply the lessons of management-discipline to government, education, healthcare, advertising and consumer behaviour, city planning, and urban-space management. In culture, such strategies often approached affect on the side of capital, not least in the work of Edward Bernays, or Walter Lippman and his 1922 performative-industrial metaphor of the ‘manufacture of consent'.40 But these social changes led some artists to examine the function of their work in terms of the social role it performed, whilst taking an anticapitalist line on the role of dreams, desires, and feelings in the production of social roles.
Previous SectionNext Section
The Manufacture of Dissent

Though most famously codified by the Surrealists, their rhetorical refusal of work was directly preceded by refusals which were tied to the imagination of other models of artistic labour. The production of non-normative labour identities and the ‘other’ objects they produced have been most clearly framed in the very different social context of revolutionary Russia. There, the situation was more open: the industrial division of labour was far less developed, whilst Communism was endeavouring to recompose the working class as part of a new society, from debates on playful/machinic movement to the free-time-as-labour of ‘subbotnik'.41 Among Russian avant-garde artists, there was both a clear rejection of the role of artist and an iterative play with naming which established a queer status with regard to art and political institutions and discourses. The identity of ‘artist’ became liminal in relation to various recompositions of artist–constructor, artist–engineer and artist–inventor:Things are hard for the constructivist production artist. Artists turn their backs on him. Industrialists wave him away in annoyance. The man in the street goggles.42Recent scholarship has explored this new identity and its labour.43 Elsewhere, performative subject-formation found direct expression in participatory mass spectacles in which new identities were literally performed. A new calendar of secular Communist holidays was introduced. Pre-revolutionary demonstrations that had been civil disobedience were reiterated as institutional urban festivals and Proletkult theatre such as ‘The Mystery of Freed Labour'. Most famously it was possible for Nikolai Evreinov to have 8–10,000 people restage the storming of the Winter Palace on its third anniversary in November 1920, watched by another 100,000; whilst Arseny Avraamov's 1922 ‘Symphony of Factory Sirens’ recomposed the machines and labour skills of an entire city as flags and pistol-shots conducted an orchestra composed of huge choirs, factory sirens, two batteries of artillery, the foghorns of the entire Soviet Caspian flotilla, hydroplanes, and a specially-built giant steam whistle playing, among other refrains, theInternationnale.44 These festivals manufactured myths of (not-yet unitary) revolutionary identities, as the People's Commissar for Enlightenment put it, ‘in order to acquire a sense of self the masses must outwardly manifest themselves'.45 He saw these revolutionary-state festivals as the telos of the popular festivals of the French revolution, themselves partial institutionalisations of rough music.46
Previous SectionNext Section
Dada and the Art of Social Movement

The scholarship on Constructivism reveals that the troubling of the role of artist by collective social engagement was clearest where there was a concomitant cycle of working class struggles troubling work more generally. Though it has been less examined in these terms, this was also the case among the Dadaists in Weimar Berlin, in a period of mass strikes and violent street battles, the Spartakist uprising and an attempted fascist putsch. Here too there was a reiteration of names and identities which reflected an attempt to forge a new presentation of selfhood and a new social role for artists. John Heartfield and George Grosz stamped many of their works ‘mont’, ‘meta-mech', or ‘meta-mech constr'. Haussman explained, ‘The term translates our aversion at playing the artist, and, thinking of ourselves as engineers … we meant to construct, to assemble [montieren] our works'.47 Meanwhile, Johannes Baader neglected his job as a trained architect and gave himself over to, in the words of his collaborator Haussman, ‘an activity which is difficult to define',48 yet continued to use the title Architekt, employing architectural construction as a metaphor for building a new society analogous to the Constructivist artist-engineer.49 The role of names in this attempt to be otherwise was also important for the mythical composition of revolutionary organisations and the mimicry/mockery of the party-form which became common among Dada, Surrealist, and associated groups; from the Dada Central Office of the World Revolution; The Anti-National Committee for Unpaid Workers; Dada Advertising Company, Christ GmbH; a tendency which continued later in Paris with the Surrealist Party and the Bureau of Surrealist Research. But alongside this focus on revolutionary identities, Dada's renaming was at the same time open and less focused than Constructivism's, for example, in their paradoxical and nebulous self-definition in terms of a broad way of acting:Dada is not limited to any art. The bartender in the Manhattan Bar, who pours out Curacao with one hand and gathers up his gonorrhoea with the other, is a Dadaist. The gentleman in the raincoat, who is about to start his seventh trip around the world, is a Dadaist.50This reflected their different relation to communism from within a capitalist society. Dada's tautologies and use of irony embodied this position of a worker opposed to capital who must be opposed to himself as capital, to the identity of worker: ‘being a Dadaist means being against Dada'.51

Kiaer argues that the presence of ‘achieved socialism’ meant that Constructivism was unique in that this made its imagining of other artistic identities ‘more than utopian dreaming'.52 But the autonomist notion of the refusal of work permits a reading of Dada and Surrealism's utopian imagination in parallel terms within Western capitalism. Western Europe did not have state socialism, but did have actually existing social movements of various kinds with their own forms of class composition, art, and culture. The Berlin Dadaists’ rhetorical refusal of the artists’ role under capital was accompanied by the establishment of various relationships with the historical vocabulary of the art of social movements. Kiaer has described how several Constructivists turned their artistic labour towards the industrial mass-production of stoves, dishes, clothing, packaging, architectural plans, and the ‘industrial agitation’ of advertising – performance as other than a worker led to an attempt to produce ‘communist objects’ which performed a role somehow other to that of a commodity. In Constructivist terms, ‘production’ replaced the art work of ‘composition’, but we might equally frame this as a move from aesthetic composition to aesthetic class composition. In the unique position of being able to enter Communist production and to do so with at least some state support, in a form that in the West perhaps only architects and advertisers were in a position to, Constructivist objects and revolutionary theatre attempted to enter the technical recomposition of working class identity. In Berlin, radical working class movements did not hold institutional power, and artists who wanted to engage with the composition of the working class lacked these official resources. Rather than entering technical composition, Berlin Dada had to begin from below, with political composition. Instead of entering the institutions of the mass-production of material culture, Dada entered the production of social movements, whose primary mode was the extra-institutional and unsanctioned collective bodily performance of subjects. Grosz and Herzfeld argued:Today's artist, if he does not want to run down and become an antiquated dud, has the choice between technology and class warfare propaganda. In both cases he must give up ‘pure art.’ Either he enrols as an … advertising artist in the army … which exploits all the world; or … a propagandist and defender of the revolutionary idea and its partisans.53
Previous SectionNext Section
Disobedient Performance

Much has been written on Grosz and Heartfield's production of montages and drawings for political newspapers, but there were other more artistically novel entries into social movement production among the Berlin Dadaists. The increased visibility of social movements at the turn of the century had multiple formal influences on avant-garde art internationally, and not least of these was on Dada's turn to performance. In Tzara's retrospective account, Dada in Zurich re-imagined the role of the artist by drawing on the traditional forms of social movement performance, ‘In the presence of a compact crowd Tzara demonstrates, we demand the right to piss in different colours, Huelsenbeck demonstrates, Ball demonstrates …'.54Tzara codified it, ‘the new artist protests, he no longer paints'.55 Albeit indoors with a paying audience, Dada took a protest-form. Their particular imagination of protest was indebted to the language of libertarian nineteenth-century working-class movements. These movements tended to account for protest and direct action in reactive terms of incitement, provocation, outrage, and offense, even after the vogue for propaganda-by-the-deed, dynamite, and assassination had passed. This language of the radical break influenced Modernists more generally, but working in these negative terms, the measure of success for these ‘demonstration’ performances was to produce an agitated crowd – the very same unruly and irrational ‘mob’ feared by bourgeois social critics. For the Dadaists, the artist–organiser was replaced by the artist–agitator, whose symbolic assault on Culture also had precedents in social movement practices, most recently in suffragette attacks on art during 1914. Later, a Parisian Dada event at the Université Populaire du Faubourg Saint-Antoine combined this form with a working-class audience, but things did not go as planned. Tzara was unable to agitate the crowd by attacking poetry. When this ‘merely elicited polite requests for explanations, he struck out against Lenin and Marx. This the workers refused to accept and though they did not break out in a riot, they held the Dadas for hours, forcing them to explain their position again and again'.56

But, in Berlin, this mostly formal artistic play with social performance moved out of the cabaret and into the relations of social movement production from which it had initially been drawn. Huelsenbeck's formulation also took protest as a performative model:The abstract artist has become … a wicked materialist … Dada is German Bolshevism … The technical aspect of the Dadaist campaign … was considered at great length. Our best instrument consistent of big demonstrations at which … everything connected with spirit, culture and inwardness was symbolically massacred.57But as this suggests, not only did the Berlin Dadaists draw more specifically on the art forms of social movements, of public parades with music, costumes, banners, stickers, and posters; but the functional framework of these forms became that shared by social movements. We might frame this in terms of their engagement with the ideas of the anarchist Gustav Landauer. Herzfeld, editing the proto-Dada Neue Jugend, published Landauer, and Jung had been a member of the Tat-Gruppe, a local branch of his Sozialistischer Bund. Landauer saw not work, but the state, as a matter of performance, ‘The state is a relationship between human beings, a way by which people relate to one another; and one destroys it by entering into other relationships, by behaving differently'.58 For the Berlin Dadaists, it was not only a case of misperforming the role of artist-worker, but also a case of artist-citizen, in a context where the public sphere was deeply threatened and contested. The Berlin Dadaists reiterated the art of activism as one of the fine arts. By increasing the play-element of their production, which Ford had excluded from factory work, they conducted an avant-garde experiment with, and re-imagination of, the art forms of social movements.

As a group, the Dadaists paraded the streets, giving speeches, inventing new slogans and putting up stickers.59 Little of this is recorded, but a photograph of Grosz dressed as Death, allegedly either before or after he paraded along the Kurfürstendamm in 1918, has become iconic. The most intense of their actions came in early 1919 during the left-communist Spartakist revolt, in which they rook an active part. The government fled, allowed the proto-fascist Freikorps to violently suppress the revolt, and elections were held in late January. Two days after the murder of one of the revolt's leaders, Rosa Luxemburg, the Dadaists began planning for a procession they organised in 15 February, which we might read as a practical precursor to their call later that year for ‘Immediate organisation of a large scale Dadaist propaganda campaign with 150 circuses for the enlightenment of the proletariat'.60 They ironically combined religious, military, and political forms of public performance with distributing a political paper, Every Man His Own Football:We hired a horse-carriage such as those customary for Pentecost outings and hired a brass band, complete with frock coats and top hats, which used to play at veterans’ funerals, while we the editorial staff, six men deep, walked behind carrying bundles of Every Man … instead of wreaths.If we incited more mockery than inclination to buy in the fashionable West, our sales rose rapidly the farther we penetrated into North and East Berlin's petit-bourgeois and working-class areas.Along the streets of grubby tenements, riddled by the machine-gun fire of the Spartakist struggle and sliced open by the Howitzers of the Noske Regime … our Dada-carnival was greeted with delight. … The periodical looked like becoming a bestseller – and would have, if we had not been arrested on our way home from serenading the government offices in Wilhelmstrasse. (We carried a supply of stickers saying ‘Hurrah Dada!’ for sticking on the walls of police cells.)61By the time they reached Potsdamer Platz, they had sold every one of their 7,600 copies, before spotting the arresting officers on Alexanderplatz. Herzfelde received four weeks in prison and a fine. Their collaborators escaped by losing their identity: the two-horse carriage covered the Jedermann … posters on its sides while the musicians left their instruments and disappeared into a nearby pub. Pageants and funeral-protests in particular were a longstanding form in social movement art but rather than a funeral for a specific figure, this played with the form, incorporating and parodying elements of the nationalist military funerals given to Freikorps members, which were regularly visible on the streets of Berlin at the time (the band played the Preußenlied, the national anthem of the early nineteenth-century Prussian Kingdom; I Had a Comrade, a military funeral-lament of the same period; and the popular song The Grassy Bank by my Parents Grave). However, travelling East they also repeated the general route of the Spatakist Karl Liebknect's funeral parade towards Friedrichsfled cemetery a month before, which had involved 40,000 people. According to Herzfeld, their own parade was joined by a few sailors. The social impact of Dada street actions is difficult to gauge now, but they were often reported in the press,62 their lives were threatened by the Freikorps and their announcement of a ‘Dada-Republik of Berlin-Nikolassee’ led to the local council having a regiment of soldiers ready to protect the district (this taking place after the failed Spartakist revolt and a short-lived fascist putsch, and apparently reiterating Liebknecht's 1918 announcement of a ‘Free Socialist Republic’ from a balcony hours after the official announcement of the Weimar Republic).63 Mehring's account above notes a more positive impact as ‘Every man his own football’ found itself adopted by working class movements as a popular slogan.

While some aspects of the avant-garde have become central to twentieth-century cultural history, this trajectory remains subaltern. Records of the Berlin Dadaists’ performances are fragmentary, and virtually non-existent when it comes to their actions in the street. Beyond the context-based ephemerality of these practices, by engaging with the art-forms and relations of production particular to social movements, they lost the historical visibility of official cultural spaces of production and have tended to pass out of art, and other, histories.
Previous SectionNext Section
Rebellious Objects and ‘Activist-Art’

The contemporary conjunctions ‘activist-art’ or ‘art-activist’ were not generally used by the Berlin Dadaists. The term ‘activist’ itself, as an ideological suffix to ‘action', referring to one who adopts the anarchist strategy of political direct action, was still a Modernist neologism in 1920 (used in the cultural sphere it perhaps also held resonances of new scientific discoveries such as Arrhenuis’ 1899 chemical ‘activation energy’). There were already cultural groups in Berlin around the journal Die Aktion, and in Hungary around A Tett and Ma(The Act, Today) which described themselves as activist, but these generally advocated models of artistic or literary ‘activism’ which treated the term in a more nebulous sense sometimes sympathetic to, but not taking the form of, direct action. More frequently, they referred to a modernising aesthetic/spiritual vitality within mediums such as painting and the use of political themes within traditional fine arts: ‘for us art is active, agitative life itself'.64 One isolated use of the term ‘activist-art', referring to these currents, can be found in Berlin Dadaist writing from 1919.65 However, in describing the Berlin Dadaists as ‘art-activists', we might employ the term ‘activist-art', not simply to distinguish the material and performative art forms of social movements from more institutional fine arts, but to describe a specific avant-gardist tendency, of which Berlin Dada is emblematic, to experiment with these social movement forms. Under this category, we might place not only their play with activist performance but their engagement with the material objects of social movements. We can read the Berlin Dadaists as experimenting with these objects’ role in fostering anticapitalist social relations, by imagining and constructing queer, provocative ‘performative objects’ which were activist in a most literal sense.

The Berlin Dadaists’ entry into social movement production primarily involved performance, but it also entailed the production of material objects. Whilst these were not art or commodity objects, they were also not the traditional folk-objects of social movement culture. Again, there is a precedent in studies of Constructivism. Constructivism's entry into mass cultural production treated objects as performative not only in terms of efficiency, but also in their contribution to the affective shaping of everyday rituals. Against the fetish enacted by the commodity, these would encourage a counter-fetish of ‘comradely’ relations.66 In contrast, these Dadaists attempted to fashion not comradely, but rebellious, objects. The forms born from the limited material–cultural resources of social movements: stickers, signs, costumes, and masks, were often tools appendaged to bodily performances. Such objects were often important in Dada performances, but the Berlin Dadaists also imagined new objects that modified the traditional objects of such movements. The most well documented of these was their engagement with the archetypal activist object of the pamphlet, in the form of Everyman His Own Football, the paper distributed during the action described above.

Their re-imagination embodied a distinct aesthetic tension, between Constructivism's Modernist industrial machine-aesthetic and the popular folk-culture aesthetics of social movements. Both evoked performance and use-value, but while folk-objects are usually tools for human performance, Constructivist aesthetics evoked use as independently embodied in the archetypal performative object, the machine. This tension was clearest in the use of photomontage, publicly employed by them for the first time in this publication.67Although as ‘montiers’ they thought of themselves as engineers, rather than drawing or designing original machine-forms Dada montage brought existing elements together, often from mass media, in shapes whose brute visible stitching identified them with handwork and popular skills rather than specialised machine-labour. This appropriation and misuse was a cultural transposition of the mode of the sabot who threw his traditional wooden shoe into the industrial machine. The Constructivists had attempted to be engineers, but turning tools into weapons, these Dadaists were first reverse-engineers. Reading this object, we might consider the section of Marx's Grundrisse, in which he argues that the fixed capital of factory machines materially embodies the ‘general intellect’68 of workers: their aggregate social skill and knowledge. Not only does this vouch for the primary compositional potential of general intellect, but it might prompt us to wonder what other, anticapitalist machines the general intellect might imagine and embody itself in. We might think of the objects and performances of social movements as just such machines, embodying labour otherwise. But the use of montage and parade-distribution of Everyman … can be understood as an avant-garde experiment with the performative potential of the social movement object of the pamphlet, projecting upon it the independent performativity of a machine. Not just by engaging new identities through the conventional symbolic hailing of posters and manifestos69 but by materially embodying the performativity of rough music. If Dada's activist performance was an affective self-dislocation of identity in order to dislocate others, they also attempted to grant this performative function to objects, which psychically implicated others in a mis-performance of their own identity.

The four-page pamphlet/paper distributed during the parade described above, Every Man His Own Football, used photomontage to visually re-engineer the form of mass-media newspaper or advertisement to serve the aims of the traditional social movement object of the pamphlet. As an object it maintained a liminal position. Although it contained committed political rhetoric, from its first page it appeared too ridiculous to be a straight political pamphlet, but was difficult to classify simply as satire. Satirical mock-newspapers were not new, butEveryman … 's use of montage and performative presentation disturbed the subject-position of its reception such that it moved from a recognisable satirical genre to a tactical subversion of the object's social mediation—a dynamic closer to, but more complex than, that of ‘fake’ news issued for black propaganda purposes (such as that airdropped on Berlin during World War I).70 Its object-ambiguity was founded on its use of photomontage to cut up and rearrange body, gender, and political identity. Mimicking the format of a newspaper, its nameplate incorporated a corresponding icon, of a dapper gentleman with cane and spectators (actually Herzfeld) doffing his bowler hat in a nonchalant greeting, seemingly not noticing that his body has been replaced by a football. Like this first absurd hailing, in the paper incitements to governmental or fascist–terrorist political participation were reiterated in the form of the fatuous calls for participation of advertising and headlines. A severe headline in a traditional heavy gothic font demanded ‘Competition! Who is the most beautiful?’ Beneath, photographic busts of powerful male government and military leaders were arranged like suitors upon a nineteenth-century style ladies’ fan, placing their struggle for power on the camp terrain of a beauty contest.71 Inside, it seemed a reactionary tendency had placed an advert, calling players for their own counter-revolutionary performance: ‘Attention citizens! For a film-pantomime, Wilhelm's Return, approximately 2,000 sturdy German men are wanted immediately. Decorations preferred'.72 This reverse-engineering of mass media advanced its distributive possibilities elsewhere by ‘Dada adverts’ taken out within press publications. Meanwhile, montage's method was oriented in Every Man … toward issues of identity-parody shared by the costumes and effigies of social movement art. But against the often serious, unitary declarative hailing of nineteenth century social movements, the front page of Jedermann … privileged apparently incoherent ‘false’ calls for participation above sincere demands. This Dada montage employed the growing access to modern mass-reproduction alongside a remobilisation of the polyphonous folk-cultural approaches associated with popular culture since the sixteenth-century, of laughter, obscenity and absurdity. This was perhaps because nineteenth-century movements had often become dominated by attempts to form party-leadership organisations, whilst Dadaist montage arose in the context of the more autonomous movement of the Spatakists, and made possible a return to the popular aesthetics evident in earlier forms such as rough music. Although less well documented, this political identity-play through a conjunction of parades and pamphlets was also employed by Baader, in releasing a ‘special issue’ of the one-off publication ‘The Green Corpse’ by showering it on the press boxes of the National Constituent Assembly before leading a children's procession around the statues of Goethe and Schiller, figures of both disinterested spiritual aesthetics and national pride.

Like some early Futurist paintings, montage's busy use of text amid jumbled bodies recalled a demonstrating crowd. The 1920 First International Dada Fair extended this aesthetic into physical space, placing social movement art forms in a gallery. Their montages were dwarfed by large slogans and exhortations on placards, which the Dadaists were also pictured raising by hand: ‘Down with art’, ‘Dada is on the side of the revolutionary proletariat!’73 The common folk and protest form of a sacrificial effigy hung on the ceiling: a soldier with a pig's head bearing a sign round its neck, ‘hung by the revolution', whilst flyers and radical newspapers were strewn about the gallery. In another photograph, the Dada Fair is presented in the form of a ‘walk-in demonstration’ that ironically placed its audience as the absent crowd, lifting the effigy above their heads and surrounding themselves with placards in a protest reflexively turned inside-out. Visitors’ chairs placed in the centre of the room solicit just this position.74 Other involuntary performances were elicited by more modest rebellious objects, now lost, in the form of antagonistic-gifts. Heartfield sent carefully wrapped ‘presents’ to soldiers on the front, ‘two shirt fronts, one white, the other flowered, a pair of cuffs, a dainty shoehorn, a set of bags of tea samples, which, according to hand-written labels, should arouse patience, sweet dreams, respect for authority and fidelity to the throne'.75 Later in May 1919, Baader, with a tone of less sympathetic antagonism, donated a large portrait of Schiller to the National Assembly via its President, inscribed with a prophecy that the Weimar Republic will be destroyed for despising the rights of the Spirit.76

Berlin Dada's cultural reverse-engineering provided influential innovations in the art of social movements. Both performances and material objects, rather than simply adopting an oppositional identity or attempting to speak from a position of authenticity or power, hybridised the roles of activist and artist, machine, and folk culture, in ‘claiming’ ironic identities – not to use them, but to implicate others in, and elicit, a misperformance of their own identity. This avant-garde activist-art emphasised material-affective, rather than simply ideological, agitation. Though they were little adopted at the time beyond the Dadaists’ circle, these objects and performances were a model of creative aesthetic experiment with re-performing and expanding the potential of what social movement theorists would later variously term the ‘repertoires of collective action', ‘framing mechanisms', or ‘constituent power’ of social movements.77 This reading of Dada's liminal art-activist practices stands in opposition to a reading of Dada as pure negation or disempowered gesture, or of Berlin Dada as a ‘political’ aberration which was no longer art. Instead, it was a coherent extension of Dada's trajectory, albeit different to the more institutional moves of Ball's Galerie Dada or Tzara's establishment in Paris.
Previous SectionNext Section
Conclusion

In Paris, although this tendency to enter the production of social movements was weaker, there were more detailed theoretical engagements with the notion of the refusal of work and the potential role of affect in social change.78 Famously, Eluard would announce ‘“Transform the world”, Marx said, “change life”, Rimbaud said. These two watchwords are one for us'.79 French Surrealist artists and writers offered several imaginations of other approaches to revolution, other valorisations of autonomy.80 Later, the Surrealist articulation of the refusal of work would find new contexts; for example, in Brazil, where Oswald de Andrade's 1928 Cannibal Manifesto re-digested Surrealist-Dadaist eurocentrism to valorise the native avant-gardism of indigenous social and cultural production free from capitalist control; and in occupied Paris, where under repressive conditions writing poetry became a subversive act for the Surrealists who published La Main à Plume on Resistance presses.81 Its title borrowed from Rimbaud, ‘I'll never work … I despise all trades. The hand that writes is worth the hand that ploughs!’82

Most notably, in the mid-1960s, Berlin Dada's avant-garde approach to social movement forms and Surrealism's rhetoric of work-refusal would be combined by a less documented other neo-Dada emerging from European and American social movements, through groups such as the Provos, Kommune 1, Diggers, Yippies, Black Mask, and Chicago Surrealists. These neo-Dadaists, who returned to the problem of reimagining the aesthetics of social movement forms of collective direct action, are the more immediate forebearers of the contemporary art-activist ‘interventionism’ practiced by collectives such as the Yes Men, Reverend Billy, and the Church of Stop Shopping, Etcetera, the Laboratory of Insurrectionary Imagination, and the Centre for Tactical Magic. The passage of the radical avant-garde into the cultural canon is well documented, and often functions as the end of the narrative. But a non-teleological account of radical avant-gardism suggests an open dialectic, in which avant-garde re-imaginations of cultural production can be reiterated time and again, both by social movements and within and against institutional contexts.
Previous Section

Footnotes


1 See for example, Blake Stimson and Gregory Sholette,Collectivism After Modernism: The Art of Social Imagination After 1945 (University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, 2007). And the debate between Claire Bishop and Grant Kester in Artforum, Feburary–May 2006.


2 Peter Bürger, Theory of the Avant Garde (University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, 1984), Hal Foster, The Return of the Real: Art and Theory at the End of the Century(MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, 1996), Benjamin Buchloh, Neo-Avantgarde and Culture Industry (MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, 2001), and David Hopkins (ed.) Neo-Avant-Garde (Rodopi: Amsterdam/New York, 2006). Bürger's own position can be seen to be modified in Peter Bürger, The Decline of Modernism (Polity Press: Cambridge, MA, 1992) and Peter Bürger and Christa Bürger, The Institutions of Art (University of Nebraska Press: Lincoln, NE, 1992).


3 I have employed the prefix ‘radical’ rather than ‘revolutionary’ to refer in less-totalising terms to that section of the avant-garde which sought anti-capitalist social change through its practice.


4 Autonomist thought develops as Operaismo (Workerism) in the 1950s and 1960s in Italy, but has parallels, precedents, and post-Operaist tendencies in Italy and elsewhere. Its first classical statement is Tronti's essay for issue 1 of Classe Operaia. Mario Tronti, ‘Lenin in England’, in Red Notes (ed.)Working Class Autonomy and the Crisis – Italian Marxist Texts of the Theory and Practice of a Class Movement: 1964–79(Red Notes/CSE Books: London, 1979), pp. 1–6.


5 By Western Marxism I intend principally the dialectical tradition, exemplified by Theodor Adorno and the Frankfurt School, which has focused primarily on critiques of art and culture. See Adorno's own defence of Modernism, Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory (University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, 1996).


6 ‘The refusal of work’ is a concern in autonomist Marxist theory which examines work-refusal in positive terms as not only a moment of the de-alienation of labour, but also as the necessary basis of Marxist political strategy and organisations: ‘The working class confronts its own labour as capital, as a hostile force, as an enemy'. Mario Tronti, ‘Struggle Against Labour’, Radical America, vol. 6, no. 3, 1972, pp. 22–5. p. 22. See also Mario Tronti, ‘The Strategy of the Refusal’, in Notes (ed.) Working Class Autonomy and the Crisis – Italian Marxists Texts of the Theory and Practice of a Class Movement: 1964–79 (Red Notes/CSE Books: London, 1979) and Antonio Negri, ‘Domination and Sabotage’, in Lotringer and Marazzi (eds), Italy: Autonomia: Post-Political Politics (Semiotext(e): New York, 1980).


7 See Herbert Marcuse, Negations: Essays in Critical Theory (Free Association: London, 1988), pp. 88–133.


8 Stéphane Mallarmé, Mallarmé: Selected Prose Poems, Essays and Letters (John Hopkins Press: Baltimore, 1956), p. 22.


9 Bürger, Theory of the Avant Garde, p. 20.


10 Bürger, Theory of the Avant Garde, p. 61.


11 Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man: In a Series of Letters (Thoemmes: Bristol, 1994), p. 107.


12 Bürger, Theory of the Avant Garde, p.46.


13 Bürger, Theory of the Avant Garde, p. 34.


14 Herbert Spencer, The Principles of Sociology(Transaction: New Brunswick, NJ, 2003), pp. 145–52 and Karl Groos, The Play of Man (Heinemann: London, 1901).


15 Louis Aragon, ‘Manifeste du Mouvement Dada’,Littérature, vol. 13, May 1920, pp. 1–2.


16 Helena Lewis, Dada Turns Red: The Politics of Surrealism (Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, 1990), p. 23.


17 André Breton, ‘La Dernière Grève’, La Révolution Surréaliste, vol. 2, 1925, pp. 1–3.


18 Bureau of Surrealist Research, ‘Declaration of 27th January 1925', in Michael Richardson and Krzysztof Fijalkowski (eds), Surrealism Against the Current: Tracts and Declarations (Pluto: London, 2001), pp. 24–25, p. 24.


19 André Thirion, ‘A Bas le Travaille!’, in Breton and Aragon (eds), Variétés. Le Surréalisme en 1929 (Didier Devillez (Fac-Similé): Brussels, 1994), pp. 41–7. Thirion would later place this article in the context of a book-length ‘Elegy to Laziness’. André Thirion, Éloge de l'Indocilité(Laffont: Paris, 1979). One might be tempted to then assume Thirion is indebted to Paul Lafargue's 1883 The Right to be Lazy, but Thirion claimed never to have read it. André Thirion, Revolutionaries without Revolution (Cassell: London, 1976), p. 170.


20 Georges Bataille, ‘The “Old Mole” and the Prefix Sur in the Words Surhomme [Superman] and Surrealist’, in Stoekl (ed.), Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927–39(University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, 1988), p. 32.


21 André Breton, Nadja (Grove Press/Evergreen Books: New York, London, 1960), p. 60.


22 André Breton, ‘Second Manifesto of Surrealism (1930)’, in Seaver and Lane (eds), Manifestoes of Surrealism(University of Michigan Press: Ann Arbour, MI, 1969), pp. 119–87, p. 134.


23 Louis Aragon, Treatise on Style (University of Nebraska Press: Lincoln, 1991), p. 37.


24 However, recently see also John Roberts, The Intangibilities of Form: Skill and Deskilling in Art After the Readymade (Verso: London, 2007).


25 This term, used by Marx to denote ‘the aggregate of those mental and physical capabilities existing in a human being, which he exercises whenever he produces a use-value of any description', is often interpreted merely as a commodity within the self-valorisation of capital. However, it should be interpreted as referring also to the capacity to produce self-valorisation and values other to that of capital, within and despite capitalist forms of production. Karl Marx,Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume 1 (London: Penguin, 1990), pp. 270–282.


26 Walter Benjamin has already suggested this perspective in his essay ‘The Author as Producer', where he looks beyond labour that ‘supplied a productive apparatus without changing it’ to that with ‘revolutionary use-value'. Walter Benjamin, ‘The Author as Producer’, in Jennings (ed.),Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings 1931–1934 (Harvard University Press: Harvard, 2005), pp. 768–82, p. 775.


27 This term first appears in Tronti's essay ‘The Factory and Society', but undergoes a series of shifts in meaning and emphasis in the hands of other theorists. See Steve Wright,Storming Heaven: Class Composition and Struggle in Italian Autonomist Marxism (Pluto Press: London, 2002).


28 Mario Tronti, ‘Workers and Capital’, Telos, vol. 14, Winter 1972, pp. 23–62, p. 60.


29 The notion of class composition has been broadened at various times to include issues of gender, sexuality, race, and ability. Thus Berardi suggests the simpler ‘compositionism'. Franco Berardi, The Soul at Work: From Alienation to Autonomy (Semiotext(e): New York, 2009).


30 Foucault develops different emphases on the term subjectification, but here it is understood as an active, autonomous subject-formation counter to the ‘constitution of subjects’ through disciplinary ‘subjection'. Michel Foucault, ‘Two Lectures’, in Gordon (ed.), Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–77 (Harvester: Brighton, 1980), pp. 78–108, p. 97. At this micro-level, we might compare the moment of subjectification to Negri's notion of work-refusal as ‘self-valorisation’ against the valorisation of capital.


31 See, for example, Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt,Empire (Harvard University Press: Harvard, 2001), p. 27.


32 These have been variously termed performative, affective, material-semiotic, or non-representational. See Judith P. Butler, Bodies That Matter (Routledge: London, 1993). Judith P. Butler, The Psychic Life of Power (Stanford University Press: Stanford, 1997). Bruno Latour, Reassembling the Social (Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2005), Richard Schechner, Performance Studies: An Introduction (Routledge: London, 2002). Patricia Ticineto Clough and Jean Halley (eds),The Affective Turn: Theorising the Social (Duke University Press: Durham, NC, 2007). Nigel Thrift, Non-representational Theory: Space, Politics, Affect (Routledge: London, 2008).


33 We can read Negri's notion of ‘self-valorisation’ and Guattari's micropolitics, as not only political but also aesthetic encounters which re-perform social relations.


34 Deborah Gould, Moving Politics (University of Chicago Press: Chicago, 2009), Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford University Press: Oxford, 1977).


35 The term ‘social movement’ refers to organisations of mass, collective direct action outside political institutions. Coined by Heberle, it has been given numerous emphases of meaning since. Rudolf Heberle, Social Movements (Appleton-Century-Crofts: New York, 1951), Alberto Melucci, Nomads of the Present (Radius Hutchinson: London, 1989), Mario Diani, ‘The Concept of Social Movement’, The Sociological Review, vol. 40, no. 1, 1992, pp. 1–25.


36 E. P. Thompson, Customs in Common (Merlin Press: London, 1991), pp. 467–538.


37 Charles Tilly, ‘Social Movements as Historically Specific Clusters of Political Performances’, Berkeley Journal of Sociology, vol. 38, 1993, pp. 1–30, p. 17.


38 Frederick Taylor, The Principles of Scientific Management (Harper and Brothers: London, 1911), p. 23.


39 Le Corbusier, Towards an Architecture (Frances Lincoln: London, 2008), p. 151.


40 Walter Lippmann, Public Opinion (Dover: New York, 2004), p. 231.


41 See Vladimir Lenin, ‘A Great Beginning: Heroism of the Workers in the Rear “Communist Subbotniks”’ in Collected Works: Volume 29 (Progress: London, 1965), p. 408–34.


42 Osip Brik, ‘Into Production!’, in Stephen Bann (ed.), The Tradition of Constructivism (Thames and Hudson: London, 1974), pp. 83–85.


43 Maria Gough, The Artist as Producer: Russian Constructivism in Revolution (University of California Press: Berkeley, 2005) and Christina Kiaer, Imagine No Possessions(MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, 2005).


44 See Frantisek Deak, ‘Russian Mass Spectacles’, Drama Review, vol. 19, no. 2, 1975, pp. 7–22 and James Von Geldern, Bolshevik Festivals, 1917–1920 (University of California Press: Berkeley, 1993).


45 Anatolii Lunacharsky, ‘On Popular Festivals, 1920’, in Tolstoy, Cooke and Bibikova (eds), Street Art of the Revolution: Festival and Celebrations in Russia, 1918–33(Thames and Hudson: London, 1990), p. 124.


46 Anatolii Lunacharsky, ‘Revolution and Art, 1920–22’, in Bowlt (ed.), Russian Art of the Avant-Garde: Theory and Criticism, 1902–1934 (Thames and Hudson: London, 1988), p. 194.


47 Haussman, 'Courier Dada' (1958), p. 42.


48 Haussman, undated typescript, cited in Timothy Benson, Raoul Haussmann and Berlin Dada, p. 130.


49 Benson observes ‘For the ‘OberDada', the ‘President of the Globe', and ‘Architekt Johannes Baader', the avoiding of the tradition of ‘playing the artist’ … was practically superfluous'. Benson, Raoul Haussmann and Berlin Dada, p. 130. OberDada, a name coined by a hostile theatre reviewer, was gleefully adopted as an absurd name for an anarchic collective. It parodied leadership itself as much as Heartfield's famous collages of civil and military leaders. Sudhalter argues this serendipity tallied with Baader's reading of Nietzsche's Ecco Homo, which presents ironic self-aggrandisement as the only means to escape even one's own system and identity. Adrian Sudhalter, Johannes Baader and the Demise of Wilhelmine Culture (New York University: New York, 2006), p. 265, 287.


50 Richard Huelsenbeck, ‘En Avant Dada’, in Robert Motherwell (ed.), The Dada Poets and Painters (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, 1989), p. 28.


51 Richard Huelsenbeck, Memoirs of a Dada Drummer(University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, 1991), p. 139.


52 Kiaer, Imagine No Possessions, p. 26.


53 George Grosz and Wieland Herzfeld, ‘Art Is in Danger’, in Lippard (ed.), Dadas on Art (Prentice Hall: Upper Saddle River, NJ, 1971), p. 85.


54 Tristan Tzara, ‘Zurich Chronicle’, in Motherwell (ed.),The Dada Painters and Poets, p. 236.


55 Tristan Tzara, ‘Dada Manifesto 1918’, in Tristan Tzara,Seven Dada Manifestos and Lampisteries (Riverrun Press: New York, 1992), pp. 3–13, p. 7.


56 Annabelle Melzer, Latest Rage the Big Drum: Dada and Surrealist Performance (UMI Research Press: Ann Arbor, MI, 1980), p. 143. Accounts of this and other performances can also be found in Michel Sanouillet, Dada in Paris (MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, 2009).


57 Richard Huelsenbeck, ‘En Avant Dada’, p. 44.


58 Gustav Laundauer, ‘“Weak Statesmen, Weaker People” Der Sozialist, 1910’, in Graham (ed.) Anarchism: A Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas. Volume 1: From Anarchy to Anarchism (300CE–1939) (Black Rose: Montreal, 2005), p. 165.


59 On their stickering campaigns, see George Grosz, ‘A Little No and a Big Yes' (1946), pp. 185–86. One such sticker can be found in Haussman's montages Dada Siegt and Dada Cino (1920).


60 Richard Huelsenbeck and Raoul Haussman, ‘What Is Dadaism and What Does it Want in Germany? 1919’, in Harrison and Wood (eds), Art in Theory 1900–2000: An Anthology of Changing Ideas (Blackwell: London, 1999), pp. 259–60, p. 260.


61 Walter Mehring, Berlin Dada: Ein Chronik mit photos und dokumenten (Verlag der Arche: Zurich, 1959), pp. 67–70 (reprinted with very minor differences in Walter Mehring,Verrufene Malerie: Berlin Dada (Claassen: Dusseldorf, 1983), pp. 178–80. Herzfeld also offers accounts, in Wieland Herzfeld (ed.), Der Malik-Verlag 1916–1947 (exhibition catalogue) (Deutsche Akademie der Kunste zü Berlin: Berlin [DDR], 1969), p. 24, Wieland Herzfeld, Die Pleite(Zentralantiquariat der DDR: Leipzig, 1978), pp. 1–2,Wieland Herzfeld, John Heartfield: Leben Und Werk (Veb Verlag Der Kunst: Leipzig, 1962), pp. 23–4. It is also described in Josef Bornstein, Das Tagebuch, vol. 10, no. 5, 1927, reprinted in Jo Hauberg, Guiseppe de Siati and Thies Ziemke, Der Malik Verlag: 1916–1947 (Neuer Malik Verlag: Kiel, 1986). My thanks to Michael White for drawing my attention to the last of these.


62 Hanne Berguis, ‘Dada Berlin and its Aesthetics of Effect: Playing the Press’, in Harriett Watts and Stephen Foster (eds), Dada and the Press (G.K. Hall: New York, 2004), pp. 67–152.


63 Raoul Hausmann, Am Anfang War Dada (Anabas-Verlag: Giessen, 1972), pp. 59–60.


64 Lajos Kassák, ‘For the Comprehensive MA exhibition, 1918’, in Benson and Forgács (eds), Between Worlds: A Sourcebook of Central European Avant-Gardes, 1910–1930. (MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, 2002), pp. 166–67, p. 166.


65 Johannes Baargeld, ‘Bulletin D’, in Lippard (ed.) Dadas on Art (1971), pp. 132–5, p. 134.


66 Kiaer, Imagine No Possessions, p. 1.


67 Montage's ‘exquisite’ disjunctive objects and bodies have been read in terms of the trauma of war, consumerism, gender, and sexuality, but can also be read through this tension as embodying Berlin Dada's encounter with social movements. See Amy Lyford, Surrealist Masculinities: Gender Anxiety and the Aesthetics of Post-World War One Reconstruction (University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, 2007), Robin Adele Greeley, Surrealism and the Spanish Civil War (Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, 2006), Alyce Mahon, Surrealism and the Politics of Eros: 1938–1968(Thames and Hudson: London, 2005), Matthew Biro, The Dada Cyborg: Visions of the New Human in Weimar Berlin(University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, 2009).


68 pp. 690–712 of Karl Marx, ‘Grundrisse: Outlines of the Critique of Political Economy’, trans. by Martin Nicolaus, 1973.


69 This model of performativity is explored by Martin Puchner, Poetry of the Revolution: Marx, Manifestos and the Avant-Garde (Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, 2006).


70 This newspaper was a very public, visible experiment with an object mediating social roles, but probably owed to Baader's early letters to public figures (the first of which was decisively employed to exempt him from military service on grounds of insanity) and Grosz and Heartfield's postcard proto-montages sent to soldiers on the front.


71 While fans with satirical designs were common in European material culture, the object itself is marshalled here for its gender-disjunctive force.


72 John Heartfield and others, Jedermann Sein Eigner Fussball (Malik Verlag: Berlin, 1919), p. 4.


73 The caption to this picture of Grosz and Heartfield holding up the placard, in Huelsenbeck's Dada Almanach, describes them as ‘demonstrating against art'. Richard Huelsenbeck, Dada Almanach (Erich Reiss Verlag: Berlin, 1920), p. 41.


74 The photograph showing this arrangement appears in Huelsenbeck, Dada Almanach, p. 128. It is fair to suggest that this is a reading, specifically, of Huelsenbeck's presentation of the fair through the 1920 Dada Almanach, in which the two photographs discussed here are the only ones of it used. However, the state shared this reading. Police and military intelligence were deployed to interfere with the fair, Grosz and Herzfeld served six weeks in jail, and others involved including the venue's owner were fined.


75 Wieland Herzfeld, ‘John Heartfield: Life and Work’, in Lippard (ed.) Dadas on Art (Prentice Hall: : Upper Saddle River, NJ, 1971), pp. 89–97.


76 Richard Huelsenbeck, Dada Almanach (Atlas Press: London, 1993), p. 139.


77 ‘Framing mechanism’ refers to the conscious strategic effort to fashion-shared understandings of the world and themselves which legitimate and motivate collective action. See David Snow and Robert Benford, ‘Master Frames and Cycles of Protest’, in Buechler and Cylke Jr. (eds), Social Movements: Perspectives and Issues (Mayfield: London, 1997), pp. 456–72, Erving Goffman, Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organisation of Experience (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, 1974). On repertoires of action, see Charles Tilly, From Mobilization to Revolution (Addison-Wesley: London, 1978), pp. 151–66.


78 Reflecting on Berlin Dada, Richter argued ‘It was not until the advent of Surrealism that a socio-political programme … was to reappear and be followed up systematically'. Hans Richter, Dada: Art and Anti-Art (Thames and Hudson: London, 1997), p. 176.


79 André Breton, ‘Preface for a Reprint of the Manifesto (1929)’, in Seaver and Lane (eds), Manifestoes of Surrealism(University of Michigan Press: Ann Arbour, MI, 1969), pp. ix–xi, p. 241.


80 See Lewis, Dada Turns Red: The Politics of Surrealism, Simon Baker, Surrealism, History and Revolution (Peter Lang: Oxford, 2007).


81 See Michel Fauré, Histoire du Surréalisme sous l’Occupation (La Table Ronde: Paris, 1982) and Anne Vernay and Richard Walter (eds), Le Main à Plume: Anthologie du Surréalisme Sous l’Occupation (Syllepse: Paris, 2008).


82 Arthur Rimbaud, A Season in Hell and Illuminations(BOA Editions: New York, 1991), p. 25.

‘Yearning for a more beautiful world’: Pre-Raphaelite and Symbolist works from the collection of Isabel Goldsmith

https://www.christies.com/features/pre-raphaelite-works-owned-by-isabel-goldsmith-12365-3.aspx?sc_lang=en&cid=EM_EMLcontent04144C16Secti...